Replicating Robert Rosen's (M,R) Systems



Ron Cottam, Willy Ranson & Roger Vounckx

Abstract
 

Much of Robert Rosen’s professional work targeted the development of relational biology and the way in which ‘efficient cause’ could be internalized in an organism. His book ‘Life Itself’ [1] focuses on precisely this aspect of living systems. Unfortunately, editorial errors in the book lead to a degree of confusion, most particularly in the case of Figure 10C.5, where Rosen’s two different relational arrows have been interchanged. Careful assessment also prompts a number of questions as to the validity and comprehensiveness of the book’s arguments.

Aloisius Louie [2] has correctly pointed out that there is a degree of inconsistency in the notation which is used in ‘Life Itself’, but if we replace its ‘morphism: domain→codomain’ mapping by his ‘element-chasing’ version [2, Figure (11)] we apparently end up with an ‘organism’ which depends on no more than one gene [3, p.265]: the majority of life’s complexity, to some extent hinted at by Rosen’s notation, disappears in the formalization. Recent research indicates that complete knowledge of the human genome is insufficient to determine human fabrication [4, 5]. Is the mathematical mapping of sets, with its restriction to one-to-one and many-to-one relationships, sufficient to describe biological processes, most particularly those relating to the complexity of genetic networks, to protein gene-switching, and to non-protein RNA-based catalysis?

Our own studies of natural hierarchy are persuasive that both organisms and rationality itself constitute hyperscalar systems, and that they always operate within birational frameworks of ‘entity and ecosystem’. How does this relate to Rosen’s scheme of internalized ‘efficient cause’, which is apparently mono-scalar and mono-rational? Rosen intentionally eliminates environmental influences from his model: is this feasible in a multi-scalar system, let alone a birational one? His relational description in terms of “entailment without states” rejects the implications of specific embodiment, whereas a birational hierarchy depends on the ‘assimilation’ of both interrelations and embodiment. We accept that Rosen’s relational model has provided a useful stepping stone to understanding the nature of life, but also suggest that it induces potentially digressive conclusions. Rosen indicates [e.g. in 6] that in a specific manner metabolism, repair and replication are interchangeable. Is this conjecture valid outside the confines of his formal mathematics?

This paper presents conclusions drawn from a comparison between Rosen’s relational model of an organism and that of a birational complementary natural hierarchy. Rosen’s model is ‘replicated’ in a number of different ways which lend credence to the argument that birationality sheds new light on the nature of life and the usefulness of his accomplishments.

Rosen’s scheme of a sequence of relational arrows can be ‘replicated’ as a nested abstract association between the hand-written code for a computer program, its compiler, and a resulting program. Both yield the same graph-theoretic description. It is noteworthy that the relevant characterization of an organism is in terms of three components – metabolism, repair and replication. Further ‘replication’ of Rosen’s scheme is as a circulation, in a triangular loop of three independent components, where on each circuit the flow is boosted by a kick from the environment; a two-component system of this kind would necessarily fall victim to dissipation. Rosen’s final well-known Figure 10C.6 appears in ‘Life Itself’ as an asymmetric diagram. When ‘replicated’ centro-symmetrically it looks quite different; the two outlying sides of a ‘figure-of-eight’ (∞) circulation are functional complements of each other; the central region ‘assimilates’ both their outcomes.

In a natural hierarchy we cannot successfully fractionate {functor and function} – it consequently makes no sense to talk about f, b/B, or φ/Ф in isolation, and we must look at Rosen’s solid- and hollow-headed arrows as related pairs, as Rosen himself recognized – as ‘functors/functions’ or ‘operators/operations’. Recognition in general of a single object implies the existence of not two but three separate domains: the object, its ecosystemic environment and their interface: the bifurcating categorization of nature into the complement of mechanism and organism is insufficient. It is important in this context to note that a mechanism can ‘contain’ an organism, but more to the point that an organism can ‘contain’ a mechanism [e.g. 1, Figure 10C.6]. An organism is not ‘the complement of a mechanism’: the complement of a mechanism is its ecosystem: an organism is the ‘complex interface’ between mechanism and ecosystem.

In our ‘figure-of-eight’ replication of Rosen’s scheme, metabolism is now the outlying f→a→b, repair is the outlying f→φ→b, and replication is now the central assimilation of both their outcomes b→f. Operator/operation f→a→b falls into Rosen’s category of mechanisms, where solid-headed arrow f→a is the induction of software flow a→b. Operator/operation f→φ→b, however, is very different: it is the opposite or complement of a mechanism: hollow-headed arrow f→φ is the induction of hardware flow φ→b. Operator/operation b→f is the intimate association of induction of software flow, induction of hardware flow, and both software and hardware flows themselves! This intimate four-fold association of birational causes and effects only exists in an organism. An organism is an intimate (complementary) coupling between a mechanism and its ecosystem.

Rosen’s model ‘does what he wanted it to do’; it (almost) ‘internalizes efficient cause’. But it is also hyperscalar, because everything is! His notational mixing of sets & elements is in fact superficially useful, in that it maintains at least an impression of implicit complexity. The next most useful step in validating Rosen’s work will be to reformulate the multi-scalar generality of a hyperscalar natural hierarchy in terms of notional mappings, to see what happens when the formally-mathematical relationships are extended to include not only one-to-one and many-to-one relationships but also the one-to-many relationships which Rosen excluded. In the absence of mutation, one-to-one and many-to-one mappings preclude evolution: one-to-many does not. Will this crude ‘injection’ of Rosennean-style complexity into a notionally-mapped self-correlating natural hierarchy convert a merely complicated mechanistic network into an organism?


Keywords: Rosen; life; organisms; birationality; hyperscale

References

[1] Rosen, R. Life Itself. New York: Columbia UP, 1992.
[2] Louie, A.H. “A Series of Unfortunate Misprints.” July 2005; http://www.panmere.com/rosen/Louie_LI_typos.pdf (23.02.2006).
[3] Wolkenhauer, O. “Systems Biology: the Reincarnation of Systems Theory Applied in Biology?” Briefings in Bioinformatics 2(3), 258-270, 2001.
[4] Mattick, J.S. “Challenging the Dogma: the Hidden Layer of Non-Protein-Coding RNAs in Complex Organisms.” BioEssays 25, 930-939, 2003.
[5] Gravely, B.R. “Alternative Splicing: Increasing Diversity in the Proteomic World.” Trends in Genetics 17(2), 100-107, 2001.
[6] Rosen, R. “Some Relational Cell Models: the Metabolism-Repair Systems.” In Rosen, R. (ed.) Foundations of Mathematical Biology II, p. 236. London: Academic Press, 1972.

______________________________________________
______________________________________________